Donate books to help fund our work. Learn more→

The Rudolf Steiner Archive

a project of Steiner Online Library, a public charity

Search results 191 through 200 of 439

˂ 1 ... 18 19 20 21 22 ... 44 ˃
130. Esoteric Christianity and the Guiding Spirits of Humanity: The Significance of the Year 1250 29 Jan 1911, Cologne

Rudolf Steiner
This continued to have an effect over the centuries. Kant was one of the last stragglers of that time, his followers were only parrot-like repeaters. Luther, however, still felt the vague influence of the evil spirits of the personality.
6. Goethe's Conception of the World: The Doctrine of Metamorphosis
Tr. Harry Collison

Rudolf Steiner
[ 36 ] Kant, who denies to the human spirit the power of understanding, in the ideal sense, a Whole by which a multiplicity is determined in its appearance, calls it “a risky adventure of reason” to seek to explain the various forms of the organic world by an archetypal organism.
The “risky adventure of reason” consists in assuming that the Earth first allows the more simple organisms to proceed out of her womb and that these then produce from themselves forms with more deliberate purpose; that from these again, still higher forms develop, up to the most perfect living being. Kant holds that even if such a supposition is made, it can only be based on a purposive creative force, which has given evolution such an impulse that all its various members develop in accordance with some goal.
Goethe, however, claims the faculty of being able to recognise how Nature creates the particular from the whole, the outer from the inner. He is willing to undertake courageously what Kant calls the “adventure of reason” (cp. the Essay: Anschauende Urteilskraft Kürschner. Bd. 34.).
80b. The Inner Nature and the Essence of the Human Soul: The Results of Spiritual Science and Their Relationship to Art and Religion 13 Dec 1920, Bern

Rudolf Steiner
There is Kant's dictum: In every science, there is actually only as much real science to be found as there is mathematics present in it. Now, my dear attendees, this is not something that we need merely believe about Kant; rather, we see it as true everywhere in the scientific development of modern times, especially in the development that most clearly and most directly leads to a world view, in the physical sciences.
But that is also what is done out of habit in our time. People liked to boast: Yes, Goethe, Kant and so on had this or that idea. But to stand up for an idea with the full power of one's personality and help it to victory is not what lives in the thinking habit, especially not in the mental habits of the present.
75. The Relationship between Anthroposophy and the Natural Sciences: Anthroposophy and Science 02 Nov 1921, Basel

Rudolf Steiner
I can only hint at these things as well. We have the Kant-Laplace theory of the earth's beginning from the primeval nebula, which is presented according to the laws of aerodynamics and aeromechanics.
But what is there for a possibility when one speaks of values that arise in man as mere ideas, but which are not the germs of future realities, what is there for another prospect than to say to oneself: We come from the Kant-Laplacean world nebula, and somehow the moral ideals emerge in our self-awareness, but these moral ideals live in us only like haze and fog.
And we see the idealities of the past as the seeds of the present world, behind the Kant-Laplacean primeval fog. The present world is the realization, the actualization of what was once only thought, just as the present plant is the realization of last year's seed.
30. Collected Essays on Philosophy, Science, Aesthetics and Psychology 1884–1901: Eduard Grimm 24 Jan 1891,

Rudolf Steiner
This doubt, by his own admission, roused Kant from his scientific slumber and inspired him to write his great work, the Critique of Pure Reason, which stirred the scientific world in all its depths.
2. A Theory of Knowledge: Preface to the New Edition
Tr. Olin D. Wannamaker

Rudolf Steiner
Johannes Volkelt had written his thoughtful books dealing with Kant's theory of knowledge and with Experience and Thought. He saw in the world as given to man only a combination of representations1 based upon the relationship of man to a world in itself unknown.
2. The Science of Knowing: An Indication as to the Content of Experience
Tr. William Lindemann

Rudolf Steiner
He already gave a fine characterization of it five years ago in his book on Kant's Epistemology, and has then carried the subject further in his most recent work, Experience and Thinking.
4. The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity (1963): The Idea of Freedom
Tr. Rita Stebbing

Rudolf Steiner
XVIII, No. 3). (Ethical-Spiritual Activity in Kant) I count his article on this subject among the most important contributions to present-day philosophy, particularly to ethics.
[ 44 ] When Kant says of duty: 48 “Duty! You sublime, you great name, you encompass nothing beloved or endearing, but you demand submission,” you “lay down a law ... before which all inclinations become silent, even if in secret they also go against it,” then man, conscious of the free spirit, answers: “Freedom!
48. Immanuel Kant: Theory of Ethics, transl. by Abbott, p. 180. The Critique of Practical Reason, Ch.
58. Metamorphoses of the Soul: Paths of Experience I: Asceticism and Illness 11 Nov 1909, Berlin
Tr. Charles Davy, Christoph von Arnim

Rudolf Steiner
It is the same with an example given by Kant;40 from a certain point of view it is justified, but during the last century it has been the source of much error. Kant tried to upset a certain concept of God by showing that there is no difference in content between the idea of a hundred shillings and a hundred real shillings.
40. Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Second Division, Book 11, Chapter III, Section 4: “The impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God”.
67. The Eternal human Soul: Goethe as Father of Spiritual Research 21 Feb 1918, Berlin

Rudolf Steiner
Goethe wanted to go over everywhere from the mere thinking to the inner spiritual views, to the beholding consciousness as I have called it in my book The Riddle of Man. Hence, Goethe is dissatisfied because Kant said that the human being cannot approach the so-called “things in themselves” or generally the secret of existence, and that Kant called it an “adventure of reason” if the human being wants to ascend from the usual faculty of judgement up to the “beholding faculty of judgement.” Goethe said, if one accepts that the human being can ascend by virtue and immortality—the so-called postulates of practical reason with Kant—to a higher region, why one should not stand the “adventure of reason” courageously while beholding nature?

Results 191 through 200 of 439

˂ 1 ... 18 19 20 21 22 ... 44 ˃